| |
Journal
of Non-Locality and Remote Mental Interactions Vol.I Nr. 3
Quantum
mechanics and free will: counter-arguments
Martín López Corredoira
Astronomisches Institut der Universität Basel
Venusstrasse 7. CH-4102-Binningen. (SCHWEIZ/SUIZA/SWITZERLAND)
Tel. 41-(0)61-2055408. Fax 41-(0)61-2055455
E-mail: martinlc@astro.unibas.ch
Quantum
mechanics and free will: counter-arguments
Abstract:
Since quantum mechanics (QM) was formulated, many voices have
claimed this to be the basis of free will in the human beings.
Basically, they argue that free will is possible because there is an
ontological indeterminism in the natural laws, and that the mind is
responsible for the wave function collapse of matter, which leads to a
choice among the different possibilities for the body. However, I
defend the opposite thesis, that free will cannot be defended in terms
of QM. First, because indeterminism does not imply free will, it is
merely a necessary condition but not enough to defend it. Second,
because all considerations about an autonomous mind sending orders to
the body is against our scientific knowledge about human beings; in
particular, neither neurological nor evolutionary theory can admit
dualism. The quantum theory of measurement can be interpreted without
the intervention of human minds, but other fields of science cannot
contemplate the mentalist scenario, so it is concluded that QM has
nothing to say about the mind or free will, and its scientific
explanation is more related to biology than to physics. A fatalistic
or materialist view, which denies the possibility of a free will,
makes much more sense in scientific terms.
I. Definition of Free
Will
First of all, we must
clarify the meaning of the term to which we refer:
Free will: a
source totally detached from matter (detached from nature) which is
the origin (cause) of options, thoughts, feelings,... That is, the
absence of (natural) laws, the existence of an "autonomous
mind", i.e. a principium individuationis.
This definition is
typical of the idealistic tradition, which relates free will with
acausality (e.g., Kant 1788). Free will in human beings is opposed to
the idea of man as a machine typical of French materialism, for
instance in L'Homme Machine by La Mettrie (1749).
Other topics which relate
to the word "freedom" are not treated here: I do not treat
the question of doing what one wants to do. This is a very simple
question and has a very simple solution: of course you are free in
that sense unless something or somebody forbids you from doing what
you want (for instance, if you are in jail). My question is deeper
than that: I wonder whether one really wants what he wants, whether
the origin of what I want is mine or is an effect of natural laws;
whether there is an "ego" separate from nature (dualism).
This is a less trivial question and this is the topic which is
referred by many classical philosophers when they debate about
freedom; Hobbes (1654) and Schopenhauer (1841) are two noteworthy
examples.
Quantum mechanics is not
metaphysics and we might think that the question of freedom of will is
beyond scientific analysis. I agree partially this statement and, as a
matter of fact, the aim of this paper is not to engage in metaphysical
speculation but the opposite: to refute speculative ideas that are
often present in science, particularly in quantum mechanics. I agree
with Richard Feynman, the famous physicist, when he says: "If we
have an atom that is in an excited state and so is going to emit a
photon, we cannot say when it will emit the photon. It has a certain
amplitude to emit the photon at any time, and we can predict only a
probability for emission; we cannot predict the future exactly. This
has given rise to all kinds of nonsense and questions on the meanings
of freedom of will, and of the idea that the world is uncertain"
(Feynman et al. 1965). Indeed, this paper is not a proposal of
using science to solve a metaphysical question once and for all; its
purpose is just to state the present-day scientific position
concerning freedom of will. Of course, there are other philosophical
analyses besides the interpretation of scientific results, but these
are not the subject of this paper.
II. Indeterminism in
Quantum Mechanics
The
discussion about freedom of will usually starts by considering the
possibility of an ontological indeterminism. Classical physics is a
deterministic model of the world. We can talk about unpredictability
but not about a fundamental indeterminism in nature´s laws. However,
the orthodox interpretation of quantum mechanics accepts indeterminism
in observables once they are measured. For example, we do not know
when an atomic nucleus is going to decay. With regard to the wave
function, y, in the interval between two
measurements, the evolution is deterministic. The Schrödinger
equation is of first order with respect to time. Therefore, from an
initial state y(r,t0)
in a fixed time t0, we can determine y(r,t)
for any position r and any time t. The
indeterminism is not present in the interval between two measurements,
only when the measurement is carried out (see, for instance, Cohen-Tannoudji
et al. 1977). There are other interpretations which do not need
indeterminism in the formulation, such as that by David Bohm (1952),
but the most extended interpretation on quantum mechanics accepts an
ontological indeterminism in its formulation.
This
indeterminism is present in all microscopic systems where quantum
effects are important and is diluted in large collections of particles
(the macroscopic state) to converge towards Newtonian mechanics,
unless there exists a mechanism in which the state of a macroscopic
system depends on that of a very few "microscopic"
particles.
How can a macroscopic
system depend on the state of very few molecules? The answer to this
question can be obtained if one applies quantum mechanics to the
biology of the human being or any other animal, particularly in the
study of the quantum systems in neurology. Ralph Lillie (1927) pointed
out possible implications of the quantum indeterminism in macroscopic
biological systems which make them different from macroscopic systems
with macroscopic components (e.g. the cogwheels of a clock) where the
indeterminism is not transmitted on each scale of the system.
Some mechanims have been
proposed to make possible an indeterminism in a brain and, therefore,
and indeterminism in the whole animal body since the nervous system
controls the movements of the muscles in the body. In particular,
these mechanisms act in the synapses, in the transmission of
neurotransmitters among the neurons of the brain:
-
A presynaptic
membrane in the terminations of the axons of the neurons controls
the triggering of neurotransmitters. These membranes are two
molecules thick and have the function of master commuter (Scott
1985) . The small size of the system makes quantum effects
important and, hence, indeterminism is present in the membrane as
well as in the neurotransmission. Sir John Eccles (1973, 1975,
1994) and Beck & Eccles (1992) back up this theory.
-
The microtubules,
protein molecules in the dendrites and the axons, are composed of
aggregates of particles which can have two different states
depending only on the position of one electron. The microtubules
take part in the control of the synapse and, therefore, the state
of the brain depends on the state of these molecules (Mitchison
& Kischner 1984a, 1984b; Penrose 1994; Rosu 1997).
III. Mind Interacting
with the Body
Since determinism and
denial of free will have traditionally been claimed to be one and the
same, some authors thought that quantum indeterminacy would provide a
new point of entry for freedom of will that was not allowed by
classical physics (e.g. Eddington 1932; Jordan 1944, 1955; Frank 1957;
Margenau 1961; Stapp 1995).
If indeterminism affects the behaviour of
macroscopic biological systems, this indeterminism will be applicable
to the human behaviour and, therefore, Pascual Jordan concluded:
"If the supposition is correct that
the controlling reactions of organisms are of atomic physical
fineness, it is evident according to our modern knowledge that the
organism is quite different from a machine and that its living
reactions possess an element of fundamental incalculability and
unpredictability. One can object that our fundamental understanding of
life phenomena is not greatly aided by considering a statistically
functioning dice cup instead of a machine as the pattern of organism.
But at the moment it is only important for us to determine in the
negative sense that the machine theory of organisms (including their
further results; e.g., in the sense of a denial of the freedom of the
will) can hardly exist in view of the new physics" (Jordan 1944).
"We can now know the behavior of an
individual organism--regardless of whether animal or man--is not
exclusively determined by mechanical necessity; we can no longer, with
LaMettrie, forbid the soul or the will to intervene in the fixed and
predetermined movements of the body's atoms" (Jordan 1955).
Among the different interpretations of
quantum mechanics, those that are based on the collapse of the wave
function by the mind when this participates in a measurement give rise
in some cases to a defense of freedom of will. This idea was proposed
by Compton (1935, 1981), von Neumann (1932) and Wigner (1961, 1967)
and other authors such as H. P. Stapp (1991, 1993, 1995), L. Bass
(1975), W. Heitler (1963), P. J. Marcer (1992), R. Penrose (1994).
Indeed, this is not a
totally new idea, this defense of freedom of will resembles
extraordinarily the ideas of the Epicureans (for instance, Lucretius' De
rerum natura), who speculate that the atoms of the body can change
their paths according to the will of the mind corresponding to that
body. Indeterminism allows the possibility of different paths and the
will chooses among them. In the contemporary quantum version, the
human will governs the body by means of the presynaptic membranes or
the microtubules in the neurons. The synaptic connections are
controlled by the mind and the system of neurons is controlled by the
synaptic connections (Penrose 1994; Horgan 1994; Rosu 1997).
There are two aspects of
the hypothesis of the mind interacting with the body:
-
The apparatus cannot
produce the collapse of the wave function in the measurement; it
becomes entangled (in a superposition of states) with the system
being measured. Hence, another kind of element is necessary to
produce the collapse of the wave function in the system
measurement: namely, the "mind" (e.g. von Neumann 1932;
Wigner 1961, 1967). Therefore, the mind can choose the state of
all the systems which it is observing. This includes
neurotransmission in the brain, which is associated with the mind.
-
All the neurons
states are coordinated by the mind when it produces a thought.
This is argued by a quantum coherence property in the brain,
non-local effects on all particles in the brain that confer on it
a unity within a unique quantum state (e.g. Stapp 1991, Josephson
& Pallikari-Viras 1991).
This is an interactive
dualism, as in Descartes (1641) or Popper & Eccles (1977). The
presynaptic membranes, or microtubules, play a role similar to that of
Descartes' point of connection between mind and body. In Popper &
Eccles, we find indeed a new version of the hypothesis of mind
interacting with the body, but they claim that the interaction is
located in a particular region of the left hemisphere of the brain
instead of all the neurons in the brain. In any case, the
characteristics of the quantum subjectivists, Descartes or Popper
& Eccles are all similar: they are interactive dualists. Some
authors who are in favour of free will on the basis of quantum
mechanics deny being "dualists" (e.g. Wigner) and prefer to
be called "emergentists", but their emergentism is in some
way concealed dualism.
IV. Counter-Arguments
(I): indeterminism does not imply free will
There are two options:
determinism or indeterminism. In the case of determinism, the atoms of
our body follow strictly deterministic physical laws, and there is no
possibility of our intervening; we cannot generate the first cause for
the motion of the atoms in our body, we are locked in a Laplacian
mechanicism that does not leave space for freedom of will (for freedom
of will as defined in the first section, not for naive popular notions
about freedom).
The case we are
interested now is the second one, that of indeterminism. Let us
imagine that quantum mechanics gives a correct theoretical framework
in which to defend ontological indeterminism (not merely
unpredictability). What about freedom of will in this case? Here,
there might be free will but not necessarily because "indetermism
does not imply free will." Of course, indeterminism is a
necessary condition for freedom of will but it is not sufficient. The
incompatibilist tradition long thought about the determinism when the
question of free will arose and argued against determinism; this led
many people to believe that determinism is the opposite of freedom of
will. Among those authors confused by these implications were those
who quickly applauded the achievements of quantum mechanics because it
opened a new door on free will.
Assuming that discussion
of free will is necessarily a discussion concerning necessity or
contingency is wrong. As Kant said, freedom is neither nature nor
chance. Philosophers or scientists who think that indeterminism gives
freedom of will forget the rules of classical logic and claim that
"(p --> ¬q) implies (¬p
--> q)", where "p" stands for determinism and
"q" stands for freedom of will. This argument is false.
For example, let us
imagine building a robot that follows random laws. Is it free? Of
course not. Indeterminism is not an absence of causation but the
presence of non-deterministic causal processes (Fetzer 1988). I mean
that "causality" is not necessarily determinism; we can
understand "causality" in a more general sense: causality as
"explanation" or "reason". An explanation of or
the reason for an event means following a law (perhaps a statistical
law), and the presence of laws is the absence of free will. Quantum
mechanics is indeterministic but it is not acausal. There is always a
cause, an explanation or reason, for any phenomenon; for example, when
an electron which is pushed towards another electron. Both electrons
are repelled, and their positions and velocities are undetermined. The
cause of repulsion is that we joint both electrons. The electrons are
not free to choose their repulsion.
Giving up fatalism
derived from scientific materialism requires avoiding any idea of
causality, avoiding any possible explanation for phenomena. When an
act or election can be explained in terms of physical laws (even
probabilistic laws), then we are including this action or election as
a natural phenomenon. Therefore, we deny that the origin of this
action or election comes from ourselves as something independent of
nature, i.e. we deny free will.
V. Counter-arguments
(II): scientific knowledge about consciousness
Any argumentation in
favor of an autonomous mind based on modern physics is gratuitous;
i.e. it is mere opinion rather than an empirically established result.
Wigner, von Neumann and many others have
pointed out that consciousness is necessary to understanding quantum
mechanics in order to avoid contradictions, but their argumentation is
somewhat dubious. The differentiation between systems that entangle
mutually and systems that produce wave function collapse when coupled
stands to reason in the formalism of quantum mechanics. I also agree
that human beings are present in a final state of the measurement,
when the results are checked. Nevertheless, I reject the statement
that mind is the agent of wave function collapse. Measurement is
associated with collapse and human beings are present in the final
stage of the measurements, but this does not imply that human beings
produce collapse.
What else can produce collapse? Is there
any alternative to the hypothesis of mind producing collapse? Yes,
there is. We can talk about collapse without making claims concerning
the intervention of the consciousness (Stenger 1997). A materialist
and reductionist position is fully consistent with the observed facts
and quantum theory. A human observer in the measurement is not even
necessary (e.g. Shimony 1988, Mulhauser 1995). There are alternatives;
for instance, the measuring apparatus coupled with the measured system
can be collapsed with the wave function in the microscopic components
when the latter is measured in a macroscopic domain. Indeed, Bohr´s
interpretation, as well as that of most of present-day leading
specialists in quantum physics, is that the central element in the
measurement is not the consciousness but the distinction between the
measured system and the measuring apparatus. A computer could produce
the measurement and the observer could read the results once they were
already obtained and saved in the memory of the computer. This cannot
be checked, since we will never know whether the collapse was produced
by the computer and the measuring apparatus before the observer
checked the results or by the human mind when the observer checked the
results (Schrödinger´s cat paradox), but at least we know that we
can interpret quantum mechanics without the notion of an autonomous
mind in the role of an observer.
We should avoid confusion between
coherence in a quantum system, in which the different parts are
entangled and mutually dependent until collapse is produced, with the
idea of a "conductor", which governs the system, as in the
case of a conductor of an orchestra. The parts of a physical system
could be compared to the musicians of an orchestra, in which everybody
listens to everybody, but the cohesion would be noticeable only for
very low energies (low temperature) or when the interaction with the
surroundings is very faint (Mulhauser 1995). Even if this was the case
in a human brain, such as superconductors with low temperature, we
have no conductor. Neither classical nor quantum physics has anything
to say about a hypothetical conductor (mind) governing the brain.
Subjectivist arguments about the mind/body problem by H. P. Stapp
(1991) based on the difference between classical and quantum physics
cannot sustain an argument in favour of freedom of will.
We must conclude that
contemporary physics has not succeeded in approximating further to a
knowledge of an autonomous consciousness that freely governs the body.
The introduction of the new notions of quantum mechanics is irrelevant
to the mind/body problem (Mulhauser 1995, Ludwig 1995). You could
adopt a subjectivist position, just as somebody could be a defender of
Berkeley´s idealism in the XVIII century, but these are simply
opinions beyond scientific debate.
Physicists have nothing
to say about the mind but neurologist do. Nowadays, most neurologists
insist that the idea of a soul or an autonomous mind is a myth. They
adopt a materialistic philosophy in which the mind can be explained in
terms of neurological processes (Crick 1994).
There are plenty of
examples to illustrate the materialistic philosophy in the
neurological sciences. Electrical signals applied to the brain produce
variations in the conciousness such as images and recollections (e.g.,
Penfield & Perot 1963). The opposite is also true: electric
signals are registered in the brain for any conscious sensation.
Indeed, electroencephalograms register activity before the mind is
aware of the sensation. For instance, in an experiment (Deeke et al.
1976; Libet 1985, 1987) in which some volunteers connected to
electroencephalograms were asked to move their fingers at will, the
apparatus registered electrical activity around 300 milliseconds
before the person was conscious of taking a decision to move a finger.
This clearly implies that unconscious activities of the brain trigger
activity of the neurons. And this means that matter governs
conciousness before conciousness governs matter. The mind cannot be
autonomous in the decisions. Moreover, it is clear that there is a
minimum time (around 60 or 70 milliseconds) for the brain to compute
the most simple sensation (Libet 1985). This time interval is too
great to be interpreted as a spontaneous decision. The neurons cannot
wait such a long time for an order from the mind to choose a state in
the neurotransmission.
The property of a quantum
coherence state in the whole brain is also absurd if we think about
experiments where the junction between both hemispheres of the brain
is cut. In this case, two wills are produced (Sperry 1964). The unity
of the brain is produced by the "neurological connections"
rather than by a property of quantum coherence. Neither can we talk
about the relation of the will (the capacity for taking decisions) to
the capacity of observing in a measurement, as quantum subjectivity
proposed. There are areas in the brain (the 24th Brodmann area)
related directly to the will and when these areas are affected the
patient can observe ("measure") but the brain cannot send
any order to the body to be moved (Crick 1994, post scriptum).
All this is experimental
evidence, not just hypothesis or speculation. And all these facts
point out that there is no autonomy in the brain, there is no
"ego" sending orders to the body. The defense of free will
is impossible in this context, and speculation about a subjectivist
role of consciousness in measurement is absurd.
VI. Counter-arguments
(III): Evolution and Ontogeny
The problem of most of
the philosophers who defend an origin of the mind in the context of
evolutionary theory is that they do not know this theory or they
forget many of its important points. Most often, they do not worry
about the origin of the mind. It is there-they think-and has
"emerged" from matter in some way; they think that the word
"emergence" solves all the problems that leave them free to
talk about the "spiritualization" of matter. The same
question arises when we wonder about the origin of the mind during the
growing of a human body through cell multiplication (ontogeny) from
the moment that the spermatozoid and the ovule join. If we forget
religious and personal beliefs, we must consider that evolution and
cell multiplication cannot explain the emergence of an autonomous mind
collapsing matter from DNA copying, which just sequences the building
of proteins in the different tissues, and mutations. It is also futile
to repeat the word "emergence" insistently while we are in
the world of "matter". The emergence of what? Of a mind that
can be distinguished from matter but at the same is generated by the
matter? Absurd!
According to the quantum
subjectivism, the mind should emerge instantaneously. There is no
place for half or a quarter of a mind producing half or a quarter of a
collapse. Either mind produces collapse, or there is no mind and
matter can only become entangled with other physical systems. This is
the position of von Neumann, Wigner, etc. Then, we must think about a
spontaneous creation of the mind. We have a baby without mind, it is
just a piece of matter. One second later, we have a baby with a mind
that can produce the collapse of the wave function in the systems
which he observes. Absurd!
The most difficult
question to solve is the paradox of the Universe before the existence
of any mind (Bohm & Hiley 1993). If the mind produced the collapse
of wave functions in matter, then nature before the existence of minds
was uncollapsed, and there was no birth of the Universe because it is
still in a superposition of states. Absurd! Further ridiculous ideas
were proposed to explain this paradox (e.g., Kafatos & Nadeau
1990) by arguing that some Universal Mind (God?) was present before
the existence of life on the earth to collapse the wave functions, but
this pantheist solution does not explain why human mind is now
responsible of the collapse instead of God´s Mind. Did He take a
holiday after our appearance? Absurd!
VII. Conclusions
-
Indeterminism does
not imply free will.
-
The opposite of free
will is materialism rather than determinism.
-
Dualism and
"mind collapsing matter" from quantum subjectivism is
against observational evidence in neurology.
-
Dualism and
"mind collapsing matter" from quantum subjectivism is
against evolution theory.
-
The contemporary
scientific position no more has a place for freedom of will than
French materialism of XVIII century.
__________________
Acknowledgements:
This article has been revised for English and style by Terry Mahoney (Instituto
de Astrofísica de Canarias).
Bibliography
-
Bass
L., 1975, "A quantum mechanical mind-body interaction", Foundations
of Physics, Vol. 5(1), p. 159.
-
Beck
F. & Eccles J. C., 1992, "Quantum aspects of conciousness
and the role of conciousness", Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci.,
89, 11357.
-
Bohm
D., 1952, "A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory
in terms of hidden variables I and II", Physical Review,
85, 166.
-
Bohm
D. y Hiley B. J., 1993, The Undevided Universe: An Ontological
Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Routledge.
-
Cohen-Tannoudji
C., Diu B. & Laloë F., 1977, Quantum mechanics, John
Wiley & Sons., London-New York, chapter 3.
-
Compton
A. H., 1935, The freedom of man, Yale University Press, New
Haven.
-
Compton
A. H., 1981, "Reinventing the philosophy of Nature", Review
of Metaphysics, p. 3.
-
Crick
F., 1994, The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for
the Soul, Simon and Schuster, London.
-
Deeke
L., Grötzinger B. & Kornhuber H. H., 1976, "Voluntary
finger movements in man: cerebral potentials and theory", Biol.
Cybernetics, 23, 99.
-
Descartes
R., 1641, Meditationes de prima philosophia, Paris.
-
Eccles
J. C., 1973, The Understanding of the Brain, McGraw Hill,
New York.
-
Eccles
J. C., 1975, Facing Reality, Springer-Verlag, New
York-Heidelberg.
-
Eccles
J. C., 1994, How the Self controls its Brain, Springer-Verlag,
Berlin.
-
Eddington
A. S., 1932, "The decline of determinism", Mathematical
Gazette, 16, 66.
-
Fetzer
J. H., 1988, "Probabilistic metaphysics", en: Fetzer J.
H., ed., Probability and Causality, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp.
109-132.
-
Feynman
R. P., Leighton R. B. y Sands M., 1965, The Feynman Lectures on
Physics, Quantum Mechanics, Vol. III, Addison-Wesley,
Massachusetts, chapter 2.
-
Frank
P., 1957, Philosophy of Science, Prentice-Hall, Englewood
(N. J.), chapter 10.
-
Heitler
W., 1963, Man and science, Basic Books, New York.
-
Hobbes
T., 1654, Of Liberty and Necessity.
-
Horgan
J., 1994, Scientific American, 271(1), 72.
-
Jordan
P. English translation: 1944, Physics of the twentieth century,
Philosophical library, New York.
-
Jordan
P. English translation: 1955, Science and the course of history,
Yale University Press, New Haven.
-
Josephson
B. D. & Pallikari-Viras F., 1991, "Biological Utilization
of Quantum Nonlocality", Foundations of Physics,
21(2), 197.
-
Kafatos
M. & Nadeau R., 1990, The Conscious Universe, Springer-Verlag,
New York.
-
La
Mettrie J., 1749, L'Homme Machine.
-
Libet
B., 1985, "Unconscious cerebral initiate and the role of
conscious will in voluntary action", Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 8, 529-566.
-
Libet
B., 1987, "Are the Mental Experiences of Will and
Self-Control Significant for the Performance of a Voluntary
Act?", Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 783-786.
-
Lillie
R. S., 1927, "Physical indeterminism and vital action", Science,
46, 139.
-
Lucretius
C. T., De rerum natura.
-
Ludwig
K., 1995, "Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical
Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem", Psyche,
2(16).
-
Marcer
P. J., 1992, "The Conscious Machine and the Quantum
Revolution in Information Technology", Kybernetes,
21(1), pp. 18-22.
-
Margenau
H., 1961, Philosophical Perspectives of Modern Science,
Yale University Press, New Haven.
-
Mulhauser
G. R., 1995, "On the End of a Quantum Mechanical
Romance", Psyche, 2(19).
-
Mitchison
T. & Kischner M., 1984a, "Microtubule assembly nucleated
by isolated centrosomes", Nature, 312, 232.
-
Mitchison
T. & Kischner M., 1984b, "Dynamic inestability of
microtubule growth", Nature, 312, 237.
-
Neumann
J. von, 1932, Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik,
Springer-Verlag, Berlin. English translation: 1955, Mathematical
foundations of quantum mechanics, Princeton University Press,
Princeton.
-
Penfield
W. & Perot P., 1963, "The Brain's Record of Auditory and
Visual Experience. A Final Summary and Discussion", Brain,
86, 595.
-
Penrose
R., 1994, Shadows of the Mind, Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
-
Popper
K. R. & Eccles J. C., 1977, The Self and Its Brain,
Springer-Verlag, New York-Heidelberg.
-
Rosu
H. C., 1997, "Essay on Mesoscopic and Quantum Brain", Metaphysical
Review, 3 (8), 1.
-
Schopenhauer
A., 1841, Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik.
-
Scott
G. P., 1985, Atoms of the living flame. An Odyssey into Ethics
and the Physical Chemistry of Free Will, University Press of
America, Lanham, chapter 14.
-
Shimony
A., 1988, "The reality of the quantum world", Scientific
American, 258(1), 46.
-
Sperry
R. W., 1964, "The Great Cerebral Commissure", Scientific
American, 210, p. 42.
-
Stapp
H. P., 1991, "Quantum propensities and the brain-mind
connection", Foundations of Physics, Vol. 21, 12, p.
1451.
-
Stapp
H. P., 1993, Mind, matter and quantum mechanics, Springer-Verlag,
New York.
-
Stapp
H. P., 1995, "Why classical mechanics cannot naturally
accommodate conciousness but quantum mechanics can?", Psyche,
May 1995, 2(5).
-
Stenger
V. J., 1997, Quantum Quackery, Skeptical Inquirer, 21(1),
37.
-
Wigner
E. P., 1961, "Remarks on the mind-body question", in: The
Scientist Speculates, I. J. Good, ed., W. Heinemann, London,
pp. 284-302.
-
Wigner
E. P., 1967, Symmetries and Reflections, Indiana University
Press, Bloomington.
|
|